Monday, September 20, 2021

On Sampling the Pleasures of Visual Culture: Postmodernism and Art - Part 1

  Robin Marriner 


 I want to explore two issues from ideas about the postmodern that seem to me to raise problems about the practices of art education. Presently I feel more confident that there are difficulties here that need to be addressed than I do about knowing how practice should be redrawn to meet them. First, I want to briefly discuss post- structuralist accounts of meaning and their implications for our concept of the art work as ‘object of experience,’ ‘object of study,’ or ‘object of knowledge.’ Secondly, I want to discuss something which, though separate, has some connection: namely the fairly ubiquitous claim (though with differing value judgments attached), that one of the significant features of the postmodern, and therefore of our present condition, is the erosion or effacement of difference between what has formerly I been deemed high and low cultures. 

 A. Post-structuralist theories of meaning 

 A1. The relationship between post-structuralism and postmodernism is evidently contentious. Where Jameson’s characterisation of the postmodern seems in part constructed from annotating certain facets of post-structuralist thinking, for example, the notion of the ‘subject,’ and the concept of the ‘real,’1 Huyssen argues that ‘we must begin to entertain the notion that rather than offering a theory of postmodernity and developing an analysis of contemporary culture, French theory provides us primarily with an archaeology of modernity, a theory of modernity at the stage of its exhaustion.’2 Perhaps we can say that if not offering a theory of the postmodern, post-structuralism offers an epistemology which is inconsistent with, or oppositional to the epistemological commitments that underpin modernist culture, and in particular modernist art culture. To that degree it seems, that if not a theory of postmodernism it is profoundly imbricated in what we understand by it. 

 A2. What is of particular relevance here both to an understanding of postmodern art practice and its implications for art education is the manner in which post- structuralist accounts of meaning run contrary to those to which modernism has covertly, or more recently overtly, had an allegiance. 

Within philosophical aesthetics, within art criticism, within art education, our thinking has been traditionally structured by certain oppositions: oppositions for example, between the object and its context; between that which is interior to it and that, exterior; between that which is essential to its meaning and that which is only contingent. Though we have different accounts of what the relationship between the interior and the exterior might Be - in some cases that the latter doesn’t count at all (for example, formalism), in others that it is heavily determining (for example, the social history of art) - in all such accounts our thinking has already posited or assumed the intelligibility of the concept of an object that exists in separation from that which .‘surrounds’ or can be brought to it. It is the legitimacy of this assumption that in their different ways, for example, Foucault in his discussion of the ‘objects of discourse,’ and Derrida in his discussion of the ‘parergon’ put into question.3 Both in effect show how that which we take or posit as ‘exterior’ to the object is a sine qua non of the object’s visibility and intelligibility to us; that which we take as contingently related to the object is necessarily related to it and in that respect not exterior to our conception of the object at all. 

To try and make this more concrete; and at the same time underscore its difference from modernist ideas, I want to look at one example of an argument in support of the autonomy of art works. 

The concept of the totally self-sufficient and/yet meaningful art work perhaps received its most rigorous articulation in American art practice and criticism of the Sixties, here I am thinking particularly of the criticism of Michael Fried and Don Judd.
Untitled 1974 by Don Judd, Plywood 36x60x60"
Untitled 1974 by Don Judd, Plywood 36x60x60"
 Though at the time the latter thought himself to be marking out ground in opposition to Fried’s modernist notion of ‘presentness’ through his concept of ‘literalness,’ retrospectively the consensus is that he was working within a modernist paradigm.4 In his essay ‘Specific Objects,’ Judd elaborates on and secures our understanding of the particular nature of . the work he is promoting (in essence minimalist sculpture) through distinguishing it from what it is not: its ‘literalness’ is spelt out in terms of its being non-illusionistic, non-allusionistic, non-referential, non-representational, etc.5 ‘Literal’ is also used within the text to signify that the meaning of the object is given by or consists in just what is there: the obdurate thing, its materials, the simple relation of its parts, etc. These two uses are taken as equivalent or synonymous to underpin that ‘… only what can be seen is there ... What you see is what you see.’6 At first glance, in fact at several glances, given how long these ideas have had a currency in the art world, a convincing case seems to be made for the idea of an object that is totally self-sufficient and meaningful: it is self-referential, literally ‘just what it is,’ and declares that. 

That there is a problem lurking here can be brought out if we remind ourselves that there is a perfectly legitimate way of describing what we literally see when we look at a Judd work as a plywood box of certain dimensions with a recessed edge, or say in the case of an Andre, a pile of one hundred and twenty fire bricks in a certain arrangement. This is not of course what Judd means when he says of the object that it is literal, that its meaning is given by what is literally there, for Judd is not talking about objects that are (simply) plywood boxes or piles of bricks but about objects that are art. The difficulty is that in the sense in which being made of plywood is a literal property of the object, literally visible and amenable to sight (which is what the persuasiveness of the argument hangs on), it seems to me that the artness isn’t. If we see the plywood box, or see the pile of bricks but are unable to see the art, there is nothing more to see, there is no further literal property that we have overlooked that is going to make visible its artness. In order to ‘see’ the sculpture what we need is something that is precisely not given in the literal/visible properties of the object: we need a familiarity with other objects, values and knowledges,
Equivalent VIII 1968 by Carl Andre, Fire Bricks
Equivalent VIII 1968 by Carl Andre, Fire Bricks
only in relation to which do the ‘literal’ properties take on the meaning of art. One might say it is only because these relations are put into play within Judd’s text, (e.g. we know what it is for something to be’ ‘non-illusionistic’), but are not overtly acknowledged, that the idea of an object that has no relations and is meaningful gains any credence and seems to become intelligible to us. One might go further and say that though when we perceive the object (simply) as a physical object, a plywood box, the relations of which I speak are exterior to the object and contingent, in so far as the object is perceived and experienced as a work of art those relations are absolutely necessary; without them the object which is the object of art, the aesthetic would not come into being. In so far as that is persuasive, those relations are then not contingently related and exterior to the object but interior and constitutive of it.7 

In a large nutshell I am suggesting that theories of autonomy in relation to artworks are highly problematic if we accept a post-structuralist account of meaning. Despite the differences (that in this context I have chosen to ignore) between thinkers designated as poststructuralists, they have in common a shared acceptance of two of the fundamental propositions put forward by de Saussure, namely, that a sign comes into being qua sign, i.e., means, in virtue of its relation to and difference from other signs within a system; secondly, that the relationship between the elements of a sign, between a signifier and a signified is not natural and motivated but arbitrary and conventional. Though post-structuralists differ from Saussure and structuralists in their rejection of the weight that the latter give to the system, (‘langue’) as the object of study, they all have in common the belief that meaning is relational. Theories that meaning can be inherent, immanent or present in/to the sign are cast as untenable because they have misconstrued the logical conditions under which meaning can transpire.

A3. One educational implication of this seems to me to be for what has to be included within the ‘object of study’ when we are studying art objects. If, as was claimed above the ‘work of art’ as an ‘object of experience,’ or an ‘object of criticism’ only comes into being in its relations, then those relations are not contingent but (logically) necessary to both its ontological status and its meaning. If we allow that ‘theory’ can be taken as equivalent to having epistemological commitments or allegiances, (rather than overt theorising), then it follows that theory is always at work in the ‘work’ qua ‘work of art,’ or the ‘object’ qua ‘object of criticism.’ There is no ‘work of art’ without theory being at work, and no ‘object of criticism’ without theory. (To claim the former, it should be stressed, is not equivalent to claiming or implying that all art works are overtly ‘theoretical’ or concerned with their own ontological status). It would seem to me that theory therefore has to be included in an art education that is to give an understanding of and access to how works mean. 

Another implication of the above is that if something takes on the status of ‘art work’ and signifies meaning qua art work in virtue of its relations, then those relations are productive in generating that art work in its specificity - as that kind of object meaning this, e.g., Andre’s ‘Equivalence No 8.’ We need to reflect further on now these relations come to pass. Rather than see talking about art, writing about art, and the other modes through which we approach and present art to ourselves as in some way mediating or translating or making ‘available’ an anterior formed (and in respect of meaning ‘complete’) object, we have to acknowledge the performative aspects of our activities. In the acts of speaking, writing, presenting slides, hanging work we are placing or locating that on which we act, we are generating relations through which the art object in its specificity is produced. (One might say the artist does the same.)8 This seems to me unavoidable, the problem is that rarely in any of the areas in which art is engaged or studied is it presently acknowledged. (I’m sure we all could cite innumerable talks, lectures, exhibition guides, catalogues, journal articles, etc., wherein, under the guise of an exclusive concern to present the meaning of work, certain relations are taken as already in place but not ‘spoken’: that is, a ‘placing’ of the work for the student/reader/viewer is effected by presenting to the student/reader/viewer a work that has already been ‘placed’ in relation to a body of knowledge or theory.) What in part needs consideration and further examination is the possible ways in which relations can be generated and put in place if certain kinds of experience are to become available/accessible ... but at least as importantly, that in our making of claims about the meaning of works we disclose that it is always in relation to some body of knowledge that they are being made: that that knowledge is itself declared. 

It seems to me that art education, criticism, shows/exhibitions cannot themselves guarantee that certain experiences will happen, nor can they (ever) offer a definitive meaning of works; relations can always change both across time and different audiences. A defensible characterisation of education, criticism and exhibition culture has to recognise that conditionality, that though my not having an experience or not perceiving meanings posited by a particular critical practice can come about through my lack of awareness of the relations and knowledges that the practice aspires to put in place, equally they can come about through a refusal of those relations and knowledges in favour of my commitment to others. Embracing particular experiences and meanings in relation to an art work always involves embracing far more than is overtly on offer. Though art culture too often operates like a ‘Goodfella,’ if not on pain of death, at least of social exclusion, it doesn’t make an offer that can’t be refused.

Sunday, September 19, 2021

On Sampling the Pleasures of Visual Culture: Postmodernism and Art - Part 2

B. High/low culture

B. The second thing I wanted to explore briefly is the purported collapse of the boundary between high and popular or mass culture, which is seen as a characteristic of postmodernism. 

B1. For example Jameson: 

The second feature of this list of postmodernism is-the effacement in it of some key boundaries or separations, most noticeably the erosion of the older distinction between high culture and so-called mass or popular culture. This is perhaps the most, distressing development of all from an academic standpoint, which has traditionally had a vested interest in preserving a realm of high or elite culture against the surrounding environment of philistinism, of schlock and kitsch, of TV series and Readers Digest culture, in transmitting difficult and complex skills of reading, listening and seeing to its initiates.9 

Or, for example, Lyotard when contrasting the effects of ideological prescriptions for culture under Stalinism and Fascism with that of recent capitalist culture, of the latter says: 

When power is that of capital and not that, of the party, the ‘transavantgardist' or ‘postmodern’ (in Jencks’s sense) solution proves to be-the better adapted to than the anti-modem solution. Eclecticism is the degree zero of contemporary general culture: one listens to reggae, watches a western, eats McDonald’s food for lunch and local cuisine for dinner, wears Parisian perfume in Tokyo and ‘retro’ clothes in Hong Kong; knowledge is a matter of TV games. (It is easy to find a public for eclectic works. By becoming kitsch, art panders to the confusion which reigns in the ‘taste’ of the patrons. Artists, gallery owners, critics, and public wallow together in the ‘anything goes’ and the epoch is one of slackening.10 

Where eclecticism and its incumbent ‘slackening’ is seen as art lowering itself into the value realm of the popular. 

Or finally Huyssen, where something of this purported change is intimated in the book’s title After the Great Divide: Modernism, Mass Culture and Postmodernism, and further elaborated within: 

The postmodern sensibility of our time is different from both modernism and avantgardism precisely in that it raises the question of cultural tradition and conservation in the most fundamental way as an aesthetic and political issue ...my main point about contemporary postmodernism is that it operates in a field of tension between tradition and innovation, conservation and renewal, mass culture and high art, in which the second terms are no longer automatically privileged over the first.11 

B2. From an art culture perspective, the above seems to be less true than is claimed. Though there is evidence that the relationship between some art culture and popular or mass culture has perhaps undergone a change, I can think of no recent work that engages with popular culture that presents itself or declares itself as anything other than art. It is situated in galleries and other art institutions, written about principally in art journals, (and when written about elsewhere - in style or fashion magazines - is always written about as art), and is made by people who pursue/demand recognition as artists. 

 As John Roberts has remarked in relation to Young British Artists: 

The new generation of British artists (with) their privileged exposure in the Eighties to the systematic incorporation of contemporary art theory and philosophy into art education have possibly been the first to recognise ... what was needed to move art onwards generationally. It would be mistaken to identify the new art and its fuck-you attitudinising with anything as simple-minded as the ‘depoliticisation’ of art. Despite much of the new art's unqualified regard for the voluptuous pleasures of popular culture (drug references and experiences and the arcana of tabloid TV being common denominators) it does not seek to assimilate itself to popular culture in fazed admiration.12 

What is perhaps different about much art that has had a high visibility in the past fifteen or so years is that it no longer seems to locate itself either in the position of critical opposition to or critical disengagement from popular culture, (or at least not in the sense that we are used to understanding that). That is, it seems to refuse the positions most commonly conceptualized within modernism (that of the Frankfurt School or of the Greenberg model) as to art’s relation to the popular. Not surprisingly in certain circles this has been perceived as the relinquishing of art’s radical heritage, of its absorption into the market (for example, on the one side by the likes of Kuspit and Gablik, on the other Buchloh). However, it is possible to give an alternative reading which suggests that what is being rejected or challenged is certain Modernists’ conception of popular or mass culture, i.e., certain concepts of art’s ‘other.’ This would be less to challenge that much mass culture is produced for the orchestration and regulation of needs and desires supportive of capitalism but that that culture is necessarily as unproblematically consumed as the accepted narratives have said. Here the difference might be seen in the shift between say the work of Burgin and Prince [Illustrations 3 and 4] and the respective ways in which they treat, and position, us in relation to the Marlboro images that they ‘represent.’ What in part at least seems to be at issue here is the idea that the commodification of an object precludes its having critical or radical effects. Or that the condition of being radical is dependent upon the eluding of the commodity form. Much art of the past fifteen or so years (and like many other recent preoccupations this can been seen as prefigured in Warhol’s work) seems to have rejected the modernist tenet that the commodity form can be eluded — i.e., to have relinquished that as a myth about art’s status — and begun its investigations from the basis of that not being the case.

US 77 (one of 12 panels) by Victor Burgin, 40 x 60", 1977

US 77 (one of 12 panels) by Victor Burgin, 40 x 60", 1977


Untitled Cowboys, 1968, by Richard Prince

Untitled Cowboys, 1968, by Richard Prince

More profoundly perhaps, much art can be read as either interrogating or rejecting the grounds on which the distinction between art objects and the objects of popular culture within modernism are made. From a certain perspective again this might be read as the collapse of distinctions or difference, (by those with an allegiance to modernism), but from elsewhere it can be read as an exploration or examination of where the grounds for that distinction are to be located. Koons’ and Steinbach’s work, for example - again, neither of whom would see themselves as other than artists - could be seen as addressing the social constructedness of those distinctions, as locating them not as an intrinsic, immanent quality of the object/work itself, as would be narrated within or assumed by modernist epistemology, but rather as in the relations between the objects and the discursive and institutional realms within which they are placed and circulated.13 

It is perhaps here that the two issues with which this paper started begin to interconnect. Not, as it may sound, because I want to suggest that many recent works can be read as illustrations or embodiments of post-structuralist theory, but rather because if read in relation to post-structuralist theory the works appear less as backsliding or inadequate than intelligible as rejecting or challenging modernist assumptions. In so far as postmodernism can be understood as involving an epistemological shift from modernism, to that degree can the works be designated as postmodern. (In fact there is evidence that many of the artists who became visible in the 80s e.g., Kruger, Prince, Steinbach, Salle, Sherman had a familiarity with recent theory.)

New Shelton Wet/Dry Double-decker, 1981, by Jeff Koons

New Shelton Wet/Dry Double-decker, 1981, by Jeff Koons


Security and Serenity by Haim Steinbach

Security and Serenity by Haim Steinbach

Of course, it's not just post- structuralists that have overtly theorised the issue of demarcating art and accounted for it as other than in the object. Despite their mutual recriminations, Danto, 14 and Bourdieu 15 have enough in common with each other and with what I am trying to suggest that they could have i been recruited to give some support. 

In short, I am trying to suggest that the implications of present theory around art, and the present practice of art are not that the boundaries within the culture have collapsed (though for some both the theory and the practice are perceived to have such implications, e.g., Herwitz on Danto: ‘the concept of pictorial object reduces to the concept of a mere conventional sign in the theoretical commerce of the world, to be variously interpreted at will,’ 16 or, for example Modern Painters or Giles Auty or Brian Sewell on practice), but rather in theory and in practice the grounds for making that distinction have been relocated. This seems to me to have implications for art education: 

First, we cannot assume that an understanding of and the experiencing of the pleasures of art culture can be privileged above an understanding of and the pleasures of other aspects of (visual) culture. Of the possible reactions to this perhaps the most obvious are: we should study visual culture rather than art or that we should study art but have to justify it on grounds other than its inherent superiority. If nothing else it suggests an area that requires further address. 

Secondly, despite what Herwitz says (above), the position argued here doesn’t mean that what we call interpretation can happen at will. Rather in order for something to count as an ‘interpretation’ already positions it as intelligible in relation to an established body/field of knowledge. To become a member of that ‘interpretive community,’ [Fish] one has to be an initiate to that knowledge. In effect every time we ‘read’ something we are privileging certain knowledges, which means there are also always (some group’s) values at work. I have tried to suggest that presently this is more often than not in denial in art cultural practice — what is presently covert should be made overt. 

Thirdly, we might say that, to an extent, different knowledges are put into play in approaching art works, (from within art culture) than are put into play in our approaching the works of popular culture. (This is not to suggest a rigid mutual exclusivity, or even anything as rigid as sometimes Bourdieu seems to be suggesting - popular cultural objects often draw upon and play with knowledges from art culture and vice-versa, but rather that to perceive something qua art object necessitates certain knowledges of the ‘field’). Within what I am trying to argue about the postmodern, differences are acknowledged (the distinction has not been effaced). What has been relinquished is the assumption of a hierarchy in that difference. (For example, Koons on the fetishisation of ‘newness’ in the art world and in commodity culture in the New Show). 

An argument for Art Education could be one for getting certain knowledges (i.e., those different from the better circulated knowledges necessary for an understanding of the popular) circulated in order that the meanings of art culture can be assessed and its pleasures embraced or rejected from a position of choice. As I suggested above, experiences can’t be guaranteed to happen. Though I’m no longer confident of the superiority of art culture’s pleasures over other pleasures, they are pleasures that I would not want to do without. If nothing else, art culture certainly enhances the range of pleasures available to us - given the condition under which many of us have to live our lives that seems no bad thing.  

Notes and References

 1.        Jameson, F. [1984] ‘Postmodernism: Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism,’ New Left Review, 146, July/August.
 2.        Huyssen, A [1986] ‘Mapping the Postmodern’ in After the Great Divide. Macmillan, p. 209.
 3.        Foucault, M. [1974] The Archaeology of Knowledge, Tavistock Publications, pp. 40-9; Derrida, J. [1987] The Truth in Painting. (Tians. Bennington and McLeod), Chicago: University of Chicago Press. See particularly pp. 60-1.
 4.        See for example, Krauss, R. [1977] Passages in Modem Sculpture, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA and Foster, H. [1986] The Crux of Minimalism, in Individuals: a Selected History of Contemporary Art 1945-1986, Los Angeles: MOCA
 5.        Judd, D. [1965] ‘Specific Objects’ in Arts Yearbook No 8. Reprinted in Don Judd [1975] Complete Writings 1959-1975. Press of Nova Scotia College, and New York Press.
 6.        Stella, F. [1966] in ‘Questions of Stella and Judd,’ Bruce Glaser,^News, September. Reprinted in Battcock, G. [1968] Minimal Art: a critical reader. Dutton and Co. NY, p. 158.
 7.        For a more detailed and thorough examination of Derrida’s ideas and their implications for our understanding of ‘art objects’ see my, ‘Derrida and the Parergon’ in Smith, P. and Wilde, C. (eds.) [2002] A Companion to Art Theory. Oxford: Blackwells.
8.         This is not to deny artistic agency but rather to suggest that it cannot itself be understood in separation from ‘theory’: that the notion of an agency or intention that is ‘artistic’ is not intelligible in separation from particular relations.
 9.        Jameson F. [1985] ‘Postmodernism and Consumer Society’ in Foster H. (ed.) Postmodern Culture. Pluto Press, p. 112.
 10.      Lyotard J-F. ‘Answering the Question: What is Postmodernism?’ in Lyotard J-F. [1979/84] The Postmodern Condition: a Report on Knowledge. Manchester University Press, p. 76.
 11.      Huyssen A. [1988] After the Great Divide: Modernism, Mass culture and Postmodernism. Macmillan, p. 217.
 12.      Roberts J. [1996] ‘Mad for it. Philistinism, the Everyday, and New British Art,’ Third Text, 35, summer (my emphasis).
 13.      For more substantial support see my, ‘Signs of the Times: Sculpture as Non-Specific Objects: the work of Koons and SteinbachArt Monthly. No 138. July/Aug 1990.
 14.      Danto, A. [1981] The Transfiguration of the Common Place. Harvard University Press.
 15.      Bourdieu, R [1993] The Field of Cultural Production. Polity Press. In relation to Danto, see especially ‘The Historical Genesis of the Pure Aesthetic.’
 16.      Herwitz, D. [1993] Making Theory Constructing Art. University of Chicago, p. 203.
  

 


Thursday, June 17, 2021

Goldin Photography and the Real

Goldin Photography and the Real

My memory of early art world comment on Goldin’s work, both other people’s and her own (perhaps following her own), was a mixture of the biographical e.g .the impact on her of the suicide of her sister, and her immersion in the world she was photographing, as a means of substantiating her and the works’ authenticity. She was a participant in the world she ‘documented’, and that acceptance of her in that world brought an access to a level of candour and honesty in the images that she presented of that world that had not been shown before.

For all the hard-working and persuasive rhetoric, there still lurked beneath for some of us a perennial disquiet about documentary photography, namely the degree to which the awareness of the documentation has affects on what is ‘documented’. Or to put it more sharply, especially in Goldin’s case given the proximity of her to the subjects in the images, (not just in the case of the earlier ones but also e.g. later Parisian ones too), there is a level of deceit, the subjects act as if they are unaware of the presence of the photographer or the camera, which is on reflection, is beyond credibility. *

(L to R) Nan Goldin, Joanna and Aurele making out in my apartment, NYC , 1999 & 

Capturing Real life, Loenke Mag, June 18th, 2017


In the latter work to an extent this is more acknowledged, i.e. and is perhaps more evidently beholden to Warhol’s influence as Goldin has claimed of her work: what we are offered in the works is a record of a given individual’s act/performance for the camera (as in the case of Instagram), not as the rhetoric claims, a record of the act per se, which was perhaps a mythic capacity attributed to photography other than where the subject was oblivious of the camera’s presence.

Though the political import of the latter- the rights of the subject - seems irrefutable what has been lost to our knowledge of the world and how what has been lost might be redeemable, re-thought rather than simply banished from photographic practice, is something that needs to be urgently addressed.( A productive starting point might be to interrogate what we think we understand by ‘the look’ as a category as opposed to looking under particular and in relation to specific circumstance).
*Ben Burbridge: Paradise Lost: Exhibitionism in the works of Nan Goldin. Photography Reframed Routledge 2018.

The largest claims about photography and its relation the real (though far themselves from unproblematic) that most recently come to mind in relation to photographic culture are those made in relation to the work of Gary Winogrand, with the weighty consecration of John Szarkowski.. But In separation from John Szarkowski’s status and institutionally designated authority in his writing little is offered by way of explanation for his judgement “No other work of the period has insisted so clearly and uncompromisingly on exploring the uniquely prejudicial (intrinsic) qualities of photographic description…The self-imposed limitations of Winograd’s art Is symmetrical with its greatest strength: absolute fidelity to a photographic concept that is powerful, subtle, profound and narrow, and dedicated solely to the exploration of stripped, essential camera vision”. (Mirrors and Windows 1978, pp23/4) “And his work has demonstrated that photography can give visible and permanent shape to experience so complex, unpredictable, subtle and evanescent that one would have thought it uncommunicable”. (Winogrand, Figments from the Real World, 1988. P 40).


(L to R)  Gary Winogrand,  New York 1961.  Figments From the Real World,  MOMA New York, 1988. P 80, & New York 1969.   Figments From the Real World , MOMA New York,1988. P93



What receives scant consideration in these accounts is that Winogrand (excepting in Szarkowski’s nodding reference to “Women are Beautiful”) is engaged in a kind of photo practice aspects of which had already become seen as highly problematic in many photographic, photo educational and critical circles. Whether we are prepared to designate the photographs as documentary or not, they are achieved by the same means as a certain form of documentary photography, i.e. without the prior acknowledgement or consent of their subjects – the extreme paradigm of which is perhaps Weegee’s infra-red photographs of cinema audiences – and raise issues about intrusion, privacy, the legitimate use of processes, and power and gender and the rights and responsibilities of those who use them.

All of us have perhaps had the experience at least sometimes of being alone in a (busy) public space, for example of sitting on one’s own in a cafĂ© surrounded by tables occupied by animated groups and intense couples; of crossing a Station Hall, or walking a street where others’ social interactions fall within one’s field of vision. At some time we all overhear snatches of others’ conversations, catch the interchange of glance and gesture, glimpse fragments of other people’s lives. Public spaces are not just the arena in which public/impersonal events are transacted, (travelling, eating etc) but that of intimate private ones too. Therein lies their fascination and their discomfort. Other people’s lives are potentially on view, but one does not know where to direct one’s eyes, for fear one will be caught looking, (e.g.by a Travis Bickle). For Winogrand at least qua photographer one can’t help but wonder if this was not his basic relation to the world. His most interesting photographs are those that enable us to stare/gaze at moments we ordinarily only glance at, - people in private in public – they give us access to a domain of fascination without fear of reprisal. In that respect we might say that they show us what the world looks like photographed, not in the way that microscopic or flash photography can give access that are unavailable because of the physiological limitations of the naked eye, but because they allow us access to a domain that social convention prohibits.

In that both their pleasure and discomfort lie. Whatever photo-theorist have told us, we all get pleasure from looking, and all photography, even when the subject acknowledges the camera’s presence turn the subject in to an object for viewing. All photography is in that sense voyeuristic, coming clean about it, openly voyeuristic photography is perhaps preferable to that that disclaims it, for in the former case we are at least forced to confront the site of out pleasure rather than bury or disavow it. Again despite what has been argued not all our looking is problematic: there are many social situations where not only is it OK but actually considered good, the look of love, at sports events, theatres, movies. The problem is not the looking but the relations within which it takes place; or better since looking is always inscribed in relations, there is no looking in itself, but like photography only kinds of looking which cannot be identified in separation from the relations within which it which it is constituted. Looking can be mutual, reciprocal one way and agreed, or not agreed, but even in the latter case it does not necessarily entail a desire for ‘mastery’ of the subject, or vicariousness, or prurience, we do/can look at others to learn, to enlarge out understanding (including our understanding of the values socially condoned and proscribed in certain kinds of looking ie. their ideology).


(L to R)  Gary Winogrand, Women Are Beautiful, (1975) Printed 1981. International Centre of Photography, & Ivar Theater, Los Angeles 1982-83, Figments From the Real World, MOMA New York, 1988. P243.

 

The traditions and practices of what we have thought of as documentary photography and a central strand of what photography is, has with the diminishing belief in the uniformity of the social become immensely problematic. Goldin’s work hardly constitutes a counter balance to that, but what is does do, as perhaps some of Mapplethorpe’s work does is to side-step the accusations about (lack of) consent and intrusion by presenting subjects who willingly assent to their mode of presentation, and like the photographers themselves are knowing enough to realise that even with diversity there is still enough of a straight majority to give what they are doing the frisson of transgressionality.

 



 

Saturday, May 1, 2021

On Not Knowing

 On Not Knowing




Two art works, one by Victor Burgin the other by Richard Prince, both consisting of photographic images from the same moment, the late 70s, both re-presenting with varying degrees of ostensible complexity and straightforwardness images from advertising campaigns for Marlboro cigarettes. In the one case the image is subsumed within a black and white documentary photographic format with text (itself not part of the “pro-photo event’’) added, in the other, any and all text supplementary to the image has been edited out from what we are presented with. Despite their sources and their destination, (the gallery system) being in common one could say that they, the artists and their works belong in different worlds.

In the Burgin work at first sight it is difficult to discern in what ways the image and text belong together. The former an image of a self-absorbed Stetson wearing male cigarette to his lips, the latter a narrative of a “dark-haired woman in her fifties” at the hairdressers*. Perhaps not surprisingly because it is not through sight that a connection is forged but through other knowledge of theories which had a currency at the time of the works making, that the elements are given a rationale. Althusser’s reconceptualization of false consciousness and ideology where the emphasis is shifted from what is represented to how we are placed/located in relation to it, how we are addressed and ‘interpellated’, (drawn into a certain space, (and what is taken for granted in that), “Ideology represents the imaginary relationship of individuals to their real conditions of existence” (153), is what Burgin is putting into play and has engaged with, (as has some others artists in their practice at this time e.g. Yates) as something that needs to be confounded. That the normal space offered to receive work is to be defeated,.. work, or better our place in the process has to ‘de-centred’. In this case the text (on the hairdressing) disrupting our normal place of reception. Additionally here given extra weight by the actual narratives evocation of Lacan’s work on the mirror phase as a fundamental moment in our formation and misidentification of self. (The initial sight of ourselves in the mirror perceived to have a boundedness and coherence that we experientially don’t feel confirmed). The image of the cowboy in (its original context) itself offering in its frontality a mirror (like) image to be identified with, here is subject to critique.


Victor Burgin, Marlbro, 1977


Richard Prince, Untitled, 1977



In comparison with Burgin Prince’s contribution to his work seems slight, he reproduces the image, or the image (in colour) minus any or its original accompanying text not unlike Warhol, and like him has by some been accused, as Warhol was (by e.g. Gablik Fuller etc. ) of not just reproducing the image but the values of the world from which it had been purloined, (in this case advertising, but in Warhol and Prince’s case advertising and other kinds of promotional pictures).

Or perhaps one could say that the work is lacking overt commentary because Prince assumes a level of sophistication in the viewer on a par with his own. Namely that the pictures without the distraction of text or without any additional text display their own non-contingent reality – that in fact the ‘pro-photo event’ and its recording are constructions (events choreographed to be photographed), not as they purport to be, events snatched from some reality quite independent of and contingent in relation to the photography. The angles of shots, the landscapes, the ‘drama’ of the action and ‘costumes’ (all often beholden to cinema), become the object of our vision. But one might say it is not just the viewer who is positioned differently in the work (from the manner of address in the Burgin), but the artist himself is dethroned. These images are offered as something with which we have a familiarity (no more or less than the artist) and as such too, like him, we can take and enjoy the pleasure of the images as images, as drama and spectacle whilst rejecting the bullshit of the ‘real’ that accompanies them.

Though both drawing from the same material, commercial images made for the advertising and promotion of Marlboro cigarettes, and presenting them in the context of the art world, in their respective treatment of that material, and in the relations that the works put in place with regard to the artists and we the viewers, as art works they separate and fall on different sides of the divide between modernist and post-modernist art.

Notes:


Althusser Louis, 1971 “Lenin and Philosophy (and Other Essays)”. New Left Books, London. p 153.

* Text on Burgin’s image reads:

“Framed
A dark haired woman in her late-fifties hands over a photograph showing the haircut she wants duplicating exactly.
The picture shows a very young woman with blond hair cut extremely short.
The hairdresser props it by the mirror in which he can see the face of his client watching her own reflection.
When he has finished he removes the cotton cape from the woman's shoulders. 'That's it', he says.
But the woman continues sitting, continues staring at her reflection in the mirror.”

Thursday, April 22, 2021

ON NOT KNOWING



HOW AND WHAT

One of the problems about trying to open up photographs, to get a grasp on how they work (at least at the level of meaning) was for a long time hampered by the concepts brought to them from literature of ‘form’ and ‘content’ which seemed from the start to fragment and divide the object which in our initial encounter we had experienced as a unity. Content was embodied in form, depended on it but was also understood as separate from it, it was what the object (photo) meant. Rather like liquid in a vessel, it could be designated as separable from its specific presentation and transferrable; in that respect form was accepted as a necessary but lightweight adjunct to the main business of visual communication, the content. Even in the late 1970s one can see Sontag battling with the same issues which as semiotics, and Barthes and Metz’s writings became more extensive and better circulated get displaced. Using the latter it is possible to offer an analysis which begin to show that what something means is at least as dependent on the “how” of what it means as much as what is shown. Using the latter it became possible to think around photographs not just in terms of what they show but how they show what they show and the part that plays in what the photographs means.    


Hollywood Movie Premier 1958

 

For example, to make this more concrete, using ideas from Barthes and Metz we can approach Robert Frank’s image Hollywood Movie Premier 1958, (Frank 1958). This black and white photograph has centrally placed and occupying about two thirds of the picture plane an image of a glamorous blond starlet, head and shoulders. Not just the caption but her clothes, hair style, jewellery, etc suggest that it is the 1950s and America or do so if one already has certain knowledge that allows that detail of recognition. Behind her at a distance, between her shoulders and the photo’s edges, at the opposite side of the (unseen) red carpet to the photographer are a line of women, in appearance much less glamorous or expensively dressed. The initially odd thing about the photograph given the then rules of good composition and clear subject matter is that the centrally placed woman who occupies most of the picture, and therefore one expects to be the subject, is (slightly) out of focus, the women beyond are sharply in. In effect, one wants to say, this is a photograph about fandom not about the movie starlet and that it is so is because of the ‘how’ of its imaging. Metz writes about what he designates as ‘specific’ and ‘non-specific’ codes that combine in an image: the former being those elements that contribute to the meaning of the image that are specific to the medium, e.g. in the case of photography, framing, depth of field, tonal values, angle of shot, etc, the latter codes that are at work in and that we have learnt from more general social experience, e.g. facial expressions, body postures, hair styles, clothes/fashion, interior design, architectural features, etc. The Frank photograph draws upon and puts all these codes into play but what makes it have the particular meaning that is being claimed here, as opposed to other possible photographs that could have been taken at the same moment from the same spot is its focus and depth of field. The same event (what Barthes calls the ‘pro-photo’ event, the event/scene before the camera (Barthes [1961] 1977) could have been shot using the same depth of field but with the actress in focus and the spectators out in which case it would have become a more orthodox image of her with blurred background, it could also have been shot with a greater depth of field in which case both she and the spectators would have been in focus. The point being that in each of these alternatives the event before the camera would have been the same, what gives the actual photograph its particular meaning as being a study of fandom is how it was photographed: how it is what is it is makes it what it is. An image is always a combination of a pro-photo event and its manner of recording, though common sense tells us otherwise (and many forms of photography, e.g. advertising, fashion, pornography play on that), the pro-photo event is not in itself retrievable from the image. Metz’s writing at this point focused on ‘signifiers’ internal to the ‘text’/image, rather than as is discussed later, how one’s reading a signifier or even recognising a signifier as such is dependent upon knowledge that one brings to the ‘text’ and the context of one’s encounter.


What is exemplified here is that the work drawn off of semiotics in relation to the visual demonstrates that engaging with images is active, involves an act of reading or decoding. This it is suggested is true of all images not especially art images, that in reading all images certain knowledges and competences are drawn on. What marks the difference on this account between high and ‘low’, ‘mass’, ’popular’ culture is not that one is engaged with actively and the other passively but the different knowledges that are drawn on in those engagements. The binaries art/mass culture, active/passive consumption become uncoupled.


Refs:

i) Frank Robert, 1959, The Americans. Grove Press. New York: 140
ii) Metz C, 1973 “ Methodological Propositions for the Analysis of Films” Screen (Spring/Summer):89-101.
iii) Barthes R, (1961) 1977. “The Photographic Message” in Image-Music-Text trans Heath S. Fontana. London.

       

     

Wednesday, April 21, 2021

ON NOT KNOWING

 

ON NOT KNOWING

Growing up in the UK in the 1950s and 1960s, at least if growing up in a non-metropolitan culturally determined area of the UK, one still imbibed certain ideas about culture, not least about “art’.  As became famously claimed a little later of a certain brand of lager, art managed to get to the parts of us that other culture had not reached. From the late 19thC, in Tolstoy’s claim that ‘’art is differentiated from activity of the understanding which demands preparation and a certain sequence of knowledge (so that one cannot learn trigonometry before knowing geometry) by the fact that is acts on people independently of their state of development and education, that the charm of a picture, of sounds, or of forms, infects any man whatever his plane of development’’(i) through to the later formalist claims of Bell and Fry, that one needed  only a sense of line colour and form to gain access/connect to art (ii), the separation of knowledge and the experience of art was well engrained in popular consciousness. Even if not a few of us felt a degree of discomfort at that: the elation and pleasure one experienced at “getting it” so easily displaced by a level of humiliation and inadequacy and anger if one didn’t: feeling one’s own muteness no less than ‘inappropriate’ comments  broadcast, even amplified one’s exclusion by/from the work.  The sharpest version of what I am trying to describe I think happened to me at the first Warhol museum show I ever saw, and initiated a change of mind that has lasted ever since about that received relationship between art and knowledge.

Orange Disaster Five Deaths. 1963
Orange Disaster Five Deaths. 1963

Marilyn Diptych, Tate Modern, 1962
Marilyn Diptych, Tate Modern, 1962

Probably the most conspicuous differences between the Warhol paintings and their source material is one of the context of encounter and scale, though also of course all the features that Morphet adumbrates. The interesting thing  about the latter then becomes (not so much their shared features with established art but the difference that those properties make to our perception of the work as opposed to our perception of the source. What I  what to suggest is that the Warhol works underscore and make it impossible for us to ignore something that  we in a sense already know but in our normal encounter with these images where we are more preoccupied with what the image references, i.e. to look ‘through’ it to the ‘star’, accident,etc, that what we are looking at, is an image. All of Warhol’s work are not just images, but literally, and more strictly, images of images, and it is that we are shown. That imaging is not a copy of the real but is constructive of what the real it to us, what tragedy, what glamour, disaster, and desirability consist in. Further one might argue that the work also discloses how those meanings (despite what has been claimed for art) are not in the pictures – which are ‘simply’ and visibly deposits of pigment on a surface – but located somewhere else. It would probably be excessive to claim that the Warhols’ paintings at that time said where, (it took the dissemination of post-structuralist theory to make that possible) but they did evidence that the meaning of a work was not unconnected with the knowledge in relation to which it was read, and at least as devastatingly to me, and the likes of me, what work meant was not granted by divine authority but determined by what (and therefore whose) knowledge was in the ascendancy at a given time. And therefore open to challenge.

 Notes:
i) Tolstoy Leo “What is Art” (1898) 1969 OUP. London. p178
ii) Bell Clive.   “Art” (1913) 1958 Capricorn Bks . New York. P 28.
iii) “Warhol” 1971. Tate Gallery London. Text by Morphet Richard. P 20.

 

A more analytic and more detailed documentation of these issues is to be found in ”Missing Warhol” RM in Art Monthly No 130, Oct 1989.